Commutative Algebra (III): Finite Modules
28 Jan 2019Let be a ring. An -module is an abelian group equipped with a scalar multiplication , sending to (usually written ), satisfying associativity:
distributivity:
and .
If we fix , then scalar multiplication by gives a map which is a (group) endomorphism of . Moreover, if we consider the (non-commutative) endomorphism ring , with addition defined pointwise and multiplication given by composition, then an -module structure on is equivalent to a ring homomorphism . This is sometimes called the -module structure homomorphism.
This alternative viewpoint is sometimes more convenient. For instance, if is a -module and is a ring homomorphism, then gets an -module structure if we define . We can verify this fact by explicitly checking all module axioms, or we could simply note that the composition of with the -module structure homomorphism gives a ring homomorphism , which must then define an -module structure.
The determinant trick
We say that an -module is finite (over ) if is finitely generated as an -module. Finite -modules are amenable to the following important “determinant trick,” which yields a generalisation of the Cayley–Hamilton theorem in linear algebra:
Proposition: Let be a finite -module generated by elements, and let . If is an ideal such that , then there exists such that
as endomorphisms of .
Proof: Let . We will first write the condition as a “matrix equation”: for each , we have
for some . Moving terms to one side, we get the following for all :
where is the Kronecker delta, and is interpreted as an endomorphism of .
The next step is to consider the determinant of the matrix . As it stands, this is not a well-defined concept, since is not necessarily commutative.
However, let us consider the subring generated by and ; this is the collection of -linear combinations of powers of . Since -multiplication commutes with all endomorphisms of , and powers of commute, the ring is in fact commutative, and we can proceed.
The matrix is a matrix with coefficients in , so it has well-defined determinant and cofactors . Multiplying both sides of the matrix equation by the cofactor matrix, we get
Hence implies as an element of . Now expanding the determinant gives us a relation of the desired form.
Note that from the appearance of the characteristic polynomial in the proof, we can recover the usual Cayley–Hamilton theorem when is a free -module and .
Nakayama’s lemma
The next result is also commonly attributed to Krull–Azumaya, and is an important result throughout commutative algebra.
Nakayama’s Lemma: Let be a finite -module, and let be an ideal such that . Then there exists such that and .
In particular, if then .
Proof: Set in the previous proposition, to get
as endomorphisms of , so . Furthermore, for all implies .
If , then implies that is a unit of , so .
Proving that a module is equal to zero might not seem impressive at first sight, but many important properties in module theory can be rephrased in these terms. For instance, a submodule is equal to the whole module if and only if ; a module homomorphism is injective if and only if its kernel is zero, and surjective if and only if its cokernel is zero; and so on. We will see some examples of this in the next section.
We can restate Nakayama’s lemma as follows.
Corollary: Let be a finite -module, and let be an ideal such that . Then there exists such that for all .
Proof: Let be as in Nakayama’s lemma, and take .
In other words, if then some element of is an obvious witness, by acting as identity on .
The most important applications of Nakayama’s lemma are to local rings:
Corollary: Let be a local ring, and be a finite -module. If , then .
Hence the problem of showing that the -module is zero is reduced to showing that the -vector space is zero, for which we have the well-developed tools of linear algebra at our disposal.
Applications of Nakayama’s lemma
Proposition: Let be an -module, and an -submodule such that is finite over . If is an ideal of such that , then .
Proof: Let . Then the given condition is equivalent to , so Nakayama’s lemma gives , ie. .
A minimal basis of an -module is a set which generates , such that no proper subset of generates ; in other words, a minimal generating set.
For vector spaces, the notions of minimal generating sets and maximal linearly independent sets are equivalent, but this is not true for arbitrary modules. For instance, viewing as a -module, no finite subset is generating, so any minimal basis is infinite; but no two elements are -linearly independent, so maximal linearly independent sets have only one element!
Also, note that two minimal bases need not have the same number of elements; for instance, if , and are two coprime ideals, then and are both minimal bases of .
However, for local rings we have the following result:
Proposition: Let be a local ring, and be a finite -module. Let , which is a -vector space, and let .
- For any basis of over , choose inverse images for each . Then is a minimal basis of .
- Conversely, for every minimal basis , the images form a basis of . Hence , ie. every minimal basis has elements.
- If and are two minimal bases of , and with , then is a unit of , so is an invertible matrix.
Proof: (1) Note that , and is finite implies is finite. Hence by the previous proposition, .
Now if is not minimal, say generates , then generates , contradiction. Hence is a minimal basis of .
(2) Since generates , we have generates .
Now if there is a linear relation among , then some proper subset generates ; by (1), this corresponds to a proper subset of which generates , contradiction. Hence is linearly independent, so it is a basis of .
(3) Let be the image of in , so . Now represents a change of basis over , so
so is a unit of . Then the inverse of is given by Cramer’s formula.
Proposition: Let be a finite -module. If is a surjective -linear map, then is also injective (so it is an automorphism of ).
Proof: We will need the universal property of over noncommutative rings: if is a (not necessarily commutative) ring, is a ring homomorphism, and is an element commuting with every , then there exists a ring homomorphism extending and sending to .
Now take , the structure homomorphism defining the -module structure on , and . Then the lift defines an -module structure on , where .
By assumption, we have , ie. , so by Nakayama’s lemma there exists acting as identity on . Hence is an inverse of , so is injective.
Comments (0)
Be the first to comment!